ภาพหน้าหนังสือ
PDF
ePub

a purpose to influence his action in a certain direction. In the notion of duty, the ethical import of which is identical with that of "ought," this conative element is not so obvious.

But,

Closely connected with the conative nature of "ought" is the imperative character it is apt to assume. though frequently used imperatively, "ought" is not necessarily and essentially imperative. Even if the "ought" which I address to myself, in a figurative sense, may be styled a command, it is hardly appropriate to speak of a present command with reference to past actions. The common phrase, “You ought to have done this, or that," cannot be called a command.

The conation expressed in "ought" is determined by the idea that the mode of conduct which ought to be performed is not, or will possibly not be, performed. It is also this idea of its not being performed that determines the emotion which gives to "ought" the character of a moral predicate. The doing of what ought not to be done, or the omission of what ought not to be omitted, is apt to call forth moral indignation-this is the most essential fact involved in the notion of "ought." Every "ought "-judgment contains implicitly a negation. Nobody would ever have dreamt of laying down a moral rule if the idea of its transgression had not presented itself to his mind. We may reverse the words of the Apostle,1 and say that where no transgression is, there is no law. When Solon was asked why he had specified no punishment for one who had murdered a father, he replied that he supposed it could not occur to any man to commit such a crime. Similarly, the modern Shintoist concludes that the primeval Japanese were pure and holy from the fact that they are represented as a people who had no moral commandments.3 It is this prohibitive character of ought" that has imparted to duty that idea of antagonism to inclination which has found its most famous expression

1 Romans, iv. 15.

2 Diogenes Laërtius, Solon, IO.

Cicero, Pro S. Roscio Amerino, 25.
3 Griffis, Religions of Japan, p. 72.

[ocr errors]

in the Kantian ethics, and which made Bentham look upon the word itself as having in it "something disagreeable and repulsive." It is the intrinsic connection between. "ought" and "wrong that has given to duty the most prominent place in ethical speculation whenever moral pessimism has been predominant. Whilst the ancient Greeks, with whom happiness was the state of nature, never spoke of duty, but held virtue to be the Supreme Good, Christianity, on the other hand, which looked upon man as a being born and bred in sin, regarded morals preeminently as the science of duty. Then, again, in modern times, Kant's categorical imperative came as a reaction against that moral optimism which once more had given the preference to virtue, considering everything in the world or in humanity as beautiful and good from the very beginning. It is also worth noting that the feeling of self-complacency connected with the consciousness of having acted in accordance with the law of duty, has no distinctively expressive name in ordinary language, while the opposite feeling is known by so familiar and distinctive a term as remorse. This is not, as has been said, “a significant indication of the moral condition of mankind," but a significant indication of the true import of the notion of duty itself.

[ocr errors]

It is not, then, in the emotion of approval that we must seek for the origin of this concept. We may undoubtedly applaud him who is faithful to his duty, but the idea of duty involves no applause. There is no contradiction in the omission of an act being disapproved of and the performance of it being praised. "Ought" and "duty express only the tendency of an omission to call forth disapproval, and say nothing about the consequences of the act's performance. The conscientious man refuses the homage paid to him, by saying, "I have only done my duty." Duty is a "stern

sq.

[ocr errors]

1 Bentham, Deontology, i. 10.

2 Ziegler, Social Ethics, pp. 22, 75

3 Murray, Introduction to Ethics, D. 108.

lawgiver,” who threatens with punishment, but promises no reward.1

[ocr errors]

The ideas of "ought" and "duty" thus spring from the same source as the ideas of "bad" and "wrong. Το say that a man ought to do a thing is, so far as the morality of his action is concerned, the very same thing as to say that it is bad, or wrong, of him not to do itin other words, that the not-doing of it has a tendency to call forth moral disapproval.

[ocr errors]
[ocr errors]

"Wrong" is popularly regarded as the opposite of right, and they are really contradictories, but only within. the sphere of positive moral valuation. We do not call the actions of irresponsible beings, like animals or infants, right," although they are not wrong; nor do we pronounce morally indifferent actions of responsible beings to be "right," unless we wish thereby especially to mark their moral value as not being wrong. An act which is permissible is of course not wrong, and so far it may be said to be right; but it would be more accurate to say that people have a right to do it. The adjective "right,' in its strict sense, refers to cases from which the indifferent is excluded. A right action is, on a given occasion, the right action, and other alternatives are wrong. Right" is thus closely related to "ought," but at the same time right" and "obligatory are not identical. I cannot quite subscribe to the view of Professor Sidgwick, that “in the recognition of conduct as 'right' is involved an authoritative prescription to do it." 2 What is right is in accordance with the moral law; the adjective "right" means that duty is fulfilled. It is true that the super-obligatory also is right. But "right" takes no notice of the superobligatory as distinct from the obligatory, and what goes

[blocks in formation]
[ocr errors]

wrong, without regarding the person who commits the wrong and violates the duty as a fit object of punishment." Cf. also Bain, Emotions and the Will, ch. 15, and Gizycki, Introduction to the Study of Ethics, English adaptation by Stanton Coit, p. 102 sq.

2 Sidgwick, op. cit. p. io6.

beyond duty always involves the fulfilment of some duty. It may be admitted to be "not only right," but not to be more right. Right has no comparative. A duty is either fulfilled or not, and unless it be perfectly fulfilled the conduct is wrong. There are degrees of wrongness and of goodness, as the moral indignation and the moral approval may be stronger or weaker, but there are no degrees of rightness.

The fact that the right action is a duty fulfilled accounts for the erroneous opinion so generally held by ethical writers that "right" is intrinsically connected with moral approval. The choice of the right alternative may give us satisfaction and call forth in us an emotion of approval. This emotion may be the motive for our pointing out the rightness of the act, and the judgment in which we do so may even intrinsically contain applause. The manner in which the judgment, "That is right," is pronounced, often shows that it is meant to be an expression of praise. But this does not imply that the concept "right " by itself has reference to moral approval and involves praise. It only means that in one word is expressed a certain concept― the concept that a duty is fulfilled-plus an emotion of approval. That " right" per se involves no praise is obvious from the fact that we regard it as perfectly right to pay a debt and to keep a promise, or to abstain from killing, robbing, or lying, although such acts or omissions generally have no tendency whatever to evoke in us an emotion of moral approval.

The concept of "right," then, as implying that the opposite mode of conduct would have been wrong, ultimately derives its moral significance from moral disapproval. This may seem strange considering that right" is commonly looked upon as positive and << wrong as its negation. But we must remember that language and popular conceptions in these matters start

1 Hutcheson, Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, with Illustrations on the Moral Sense, p. 279. Clifford, Lectures and

Essays, pp. 294, 304 sq.

Fowler and Wilson, Principles of Morals, ii. 199. Alexander, Moral Order and Progress, p. 399.

from the notion of a moral rule or command. It is a matter of paramount importance that such modes of conduct as are apt to arouse moral indignation should be avoided. People try to prevent them by prohibitions and injunctions, often emphasised by threats of penalties for the transgressors. The whole moral and social discipline is based upon commands; customs are rules of conduct, and so are laws. It is natural, then, that the notion of a command should figure uppermost in popular conceptions of morality. Obedience to the command is right, a breach of it is wrong. But the fact which gives birth to the command itself is the indignation called forth by the act which the command forbids, or by the omission of that which it enjoins.

I have spoken here of "right" as an adjective. Used as a substantive, to denote a right, it also, in whatever sense it be used, expresses a concept which is rooted in the emotion of moral disapproval. To have a right to do a thing is to be allowed to do it, either by positive law, in the case of a legal right, or by the moral law, in the case of a moral right; in other words, to have a moral right to do a thing means that it is not wrong to do it. But generally the concept of "a right" means something more than this. From the fact that an act is allowable, that it is not wrong, it follows, as a rule, that it ought not to be prevented, that no hindrance ought to be put in the way of its performance; and this character of inviolability is largely included in the very concepts of rights. That a man has a right to live does not merely mean that he commits no wrong by supporting his life, but it chiefly means that it would be wrong of other people to prevent him from living, that it is their duty not to kill him, or even, as the case may be, that it is their duty to help him to live. And in order to constitute a right in him, the duty in question must be a duty to him. That a right belonging to A is not merely a duty incumbent on B, but a duty to A incumbent on B, will become evident from an example. To kill another

« ก่อนหน้าดำเนินการต่อ
 »