ภาพหน้าหนังสือ
PDF
ePub

We may feel disinterested resentment, or disinterested retributive kindly emotion,

on account of an injury inflicted, or a benefit conferred, upon another person

with whose pain, or pleasure, we sympathise, and in whose welfare we take a

kindly interest, p. 108.-Sympathetic feelings based on association, p. 109

sq.-Only when aided by the altruistic sentiment sympathy induces us to take

a kindly interest in the feelings of our neighbours, and tends to produce

disinterested retributive emotions, p. 110 sq. —Sympathetic resentment to be

found in all animal species which possess altruistic sentiments, p. 111 sq.-

Sympathetic resentment among savages, p. 113 sq.-Sympathetic resentment

may not only be a reaction against sympathetic pain, but may be directly

produced by the cognition of the signs of anger (punishment, language, &c.),

pp. 114-116.-Disinterested antipathies, p. 116 sq.-Sympathy springing

from an altruistic sentiment may also produce disinterested kindly emotion,

p. 117. Disinterested likings, ibid.-Why disinterestedness, apparent im-

partiality, and the flavour of generality have become characteristics by

which so-called moral emotions are distinguished from other retributive

emotions, p. 117 sq.-Custom not only a public habit, but a rule of conduct,

p. 118.—Custom conceived of as a moral rule, p. 118 sq.-In early society

customs the only moral rules ever thought of, p. 119.-The characteristics of

moral indignation to be sought for in its connection with custom, p. 120.-

Custom characterised by generality, disinterestedness, and apparent im-

partiality, p. 120 sq.-Public indignation lies at the bottom of custom as a

moral rule, p. 121 sq.-As public indignation is the prototype of moral dis-

approval, so public approval is the prototype of moral approval, p. 122.—

Moral disapproval and approval have not always remained inseparably con-

nected with the feelings of any special society, p. 122 sq.-Yet they remain

to the last public emotions-if not in reality, then as an ideal, p. 123.—

Refutation of the opinion that the original form of the moral consciousness

has been the individual's own conscience, p. 123 sq.—The antiquity of moral

resentment, p. 124.—The supposition that remorse is unknown among the

lower races contradicted by facts, p. 124 sq.-Criticism of Lord Avebury's {

statement that modern savages seem to be almost entirely wanting in

moral feeling, pp. 125–129. —The antiquity of moral approval, p. 129 sq.

How we can get an insight into the moral ideas of mankind at large, p. 158.-The

close connection between the habitualness and the obligatoriness of custom,

p. 159.-Though every public habit is not a custom, involving an obligation,

men's standard of morality is not independent of their practice, p. 159 sq.-

The study of moral ideas to a large extent a study of customs, p. 160.-But

custom never covers the whole field of morality, and the uncovered space

grows larger in proportion as the moral consciousness develops, p. 160 sq.-

At the lower stages of civilisation custom the sole rule for conduct, p. 161.-

Even kings described as autocrats tied by custom, p. 162.-In competition with

law custom frequently carries the day, p. 163 sq.-Custom stronger than law

and religion combined, p. 164.-The laws themselves command obedience

more as customs than as laws, ibid.-Many laws were customs before they

became laws, p. 165.—The transformation of customs into laws, p. 165 sq.-

Laws as expressions of moral ideas, pp. 166-168.—Punishment and indemni-

fication, p. 168 sq.-Definition of punishment, p. 169 sq.-Savage punishments

inflicted upon the culprit by the community at large, pp. 170-173.-By some

person or persons invested with judicial authority, pp. 173-175.-The develop-

ment of judicial organisation out of a previous system of lynch-law, p. 175.—

Out of a previous system of private revenge, p. 176.-Public indignation

displays itself not only in punishment, but to a certain extent in the custom of

revenge, p. 176 sq.—The social origin of the lex talionis, pp. 177–180.-The

transition from revenge to punishment, and the establishment of a central judi-

cial and executive authority, pp. 180-183.-The jurisdiction of chiefs, p. 183 sq.

-The injured party or the accuser acting as executioner, but not as judge,

p. 184 sq.-The existence of punishment and judicial organisation among a

certain people no exact index to its general state of culture, p. 185.—The

supposition that punishment has been intended to act as a deterrent, p. 185 sq.

-Among various semi-civilised and civilised peoples the criminal law has

assumed a severity which far surpasses the rigour of the lex talionis, pp. 186–

188.-Wanton cruelty not a general characteristic of the public justice of

savages, pp. 188-190. --Legislators referring to the deterrent effects of punish-

ment, p. 190 sq.-The practice of punishing criminals in public, p. 191 sq.-

The punishment actually inflicted on the criminal in many cases much less

severe than the punishment with which the law threatens him, p. 192 sq.-

The detection of criminals was in earlier times much rarer and more uncertain

than it is now, p. 193.—The chief explanation of the great severity of certain

THE GENERAL NATURE OF THE SUBJECTS OF ENLIGHTENED

MORAL JUDGMENTS

Definitions of the term ""
conduct," p. 202 sq.-The meaning of the word " act,"

p. 203 sq.-The meaning of the word "intention,” p. 204.—There can be

only one intention in one act, p. 204 sq.-The moral judgments which we

pass on acts do not really relate to the event, but to the intention, p. 205 sq.

-A person morally accountable also for his deliberate wishes, p. 206.—A

deliberate wish is a volition, p. 206 sq.-The meaning of the word “ motive,"

p. 207.-Motives which are volitions fall within the sphere of moral valuation,

ibid.—The motive of an act may be an intention, but an intention belonging

to another act, ibid.-Even motives which consist of non-volitional cona-

tions may indirectly exercise much influence on moral judgments, p.

207 sq.-Refutation of Mill's statement that "the motive has nothing to

do with the morality of the action," p. 208 sq.-Moral judgments really

passed upon men as acting or willing, not upon acts or volitions in the abstract,

p. 209.-Forbearances morally equivalent to acts, p. 209 sq.-Distinction

between forbearances and omissions, p. 210.-Moral judgments refer not

only to willing, but to not-willing as well, not only to acts and forbearances,

but to omissions, p. 210 sq.-Negligence, heedlessness, and rashness, p. 211.

-Moral judgments of blame concerned with not-willing only in so far as this
not-willing is attributed to a defect of the "will," p. 211 sq.-Distinction
between conscious omissions and forbearances, and between not-willing to
refrain from doing and willing to do, p. 212.-The "known concomitants of
acts," p. 213.-Absence of volitions also gives rise to moral praise, p. 213 sq.
-The meaning of the term "conduct," p. 214.-The subject of a moral
judgment is, strictly speaking, a person's will, or character, conceived as the
cause either of volitions or of the absence of volitions, p. 214 sq.-Moral judg-
ments that are passed on emotions or opinions really refer to the will, p. 215 sq.

-

An agent not responsible for anything which he could not be aware of, p. 249.-

The irresponsibility of animals, pp. 249-251.- Resentment towards an

animal which has caused some injury, p. 251.—At the lower stages of civilisa-

tion animals deliberately treated as responsible beings, ibid.-The custom of

blood-revenge extended to the animal world, pp. 251-253.-Animals exposed

to regular punishment, pp. 253-255.-The origin of the medieval practice of

punishing animals, p. 255 sq.-Explanation of the practice of retaliating upon

animals, pp. 256-260.-At the earlier stages of civilisation even inanimate

things treated as if they were responsible agents, pp. 260-262.—Explanation

of this, pp. 262-264.-The total or partial irresponsibility of childhood

and early youth, pp. 264-267.-According to early custom, children some-

times subject to the rule of retaliation, p. 267.-Parents responsible for the

deeds of their children, p. 267 sq.-In Europe there has been a tendency to

raise the age at which full legal responsibility commences, p. 268 sq.—The

irresponsibility of idiots and madmen, p. 269 sq.-Idiots and insane persons

objects of religious reverence, p. 270 sq.-Lunatics treated with great severity

or punished for their deeds, pp. 271-274.-Explanation of this, p. 274 sq.-

The ignorance of which lunatics have been victims in the hands of lawyers,

pp. 275-277.-The total or partial irresponsibility of intoxicated persons,

p. 277 sq.-Drunkenness recognised as a ground of extenuation, pp. 278-280.

-Not recognised as a ground of extenuation, p. 280 sq.—Explanation of
these facts, p. 281 sq.

Why in early moral codes the so-called negative commandments are much more

prominent than the positive commandments, p. 303.--The little cognisance

which the criminal laws of civilised nations take of forbearances and omis-

sions, p. 303 sq.-The more scrutinising the moral consciousness, the greater

the importance which it attaches to positive commandments, p. 304 sq.-Yet

the customs of all nations contain not only prohibitions, but positive injunc

tions as well, p. 305. -The unreflecting mind apt to exaggerate the guilt of

a person who out of heedlessness or rashness causes harm by a positive act,

ibid.-Early custom and law may be anxious enough to trace an event to

its source, pp. 305-307.-But they easily fail to discover where there is guilt

or not, and, in case of carelessness, to determine the magnitude of the

offender's guilt, p. 307 sq.-The opinion that a person is answerable for all

the damage which directly ensues from an act of his, even though no foresight

could have reasonably been expected to look out for it, p. 308 sq.—On the

other hand, little or no censure passed on him whose want of foresight or

want of self-restraint is productive of suffering, if only the effect is sufficiently

remote, p. 309 sq.-The moral emotions may as naturally give rise to judg-

ments on human character as to judgments on human conduct, p. 310.-Even

when a moral judgment immediately refers to a distinct act, it takes notice of

the agent's will as a whole, p. 310 sq.-The practice of punishing a second or

third offence more severely than the first, p. 311 sq.-The more a moral

judgment is influenced by reflection, the more it scrutinises the character

which manifests itself in that individual piece of conduct by which the judg-

ment is occasioned, p. 312 sq.-But however superficial it be, it always refers

to a will conceived of as a continuous entity, p. 313.

« ก่อนหน้าดำเนินการต่อ
 »